Orthoexistence gives greater depth to thething-in-itself without leaving it
entirely in itself. Orthoexistencemay be approached via science,
though it is not certainthat this way will lead to a thorough understanding.
Such a viewgives more way to science, to a scientific insight into existence
than Kant's vision does, for it is in the aftermath of present-dayscience
in as much as it accepts space and time as being objective.Science tends to
delve into the thing-in-itself, to cognizeit, whereas Kant drove it so
far from us that we can no longerhope to have an insight into any of its
profundities.
By rejecting the objectiveness of space andtime Kant has naturally paved the
way for the thing-in-itself.Existence could get free of absurdity to become a
thing-in-itself.The problems of the infinite or finite physical space or time
are no longer raised for they are pure conceptions.
Kant could not deny existence as a whole,so he abstracted space and time thereof
and treated them as apriori intuitions. In this way he thought of the
thing-in-itselfin isolation, and focussed on the subject to the detriment of
the object. From the existence of the object, the subject is thusonly left the
phenomena he deals with, of course, depending onthe initial extrusion of the
thing-in itself. According to Kant,we can forget the thing-in-itself because we
and the whole bulkof our science deal with phenomena. Otherwise stated, the
objectiveworld we are dealing with is the world of phenomena. The thing-in-itself
is something singular, which may be of no interest at all as faras we cannot
reach it. However, this should not lead to the far-fetchedconclusion that it
does not exist for then the whole system wouldcollapse. The thing-in-itself is a
ground for any mental schemeand in case we forget it, which is possible, as far
as we do notnor can cognize anything about it, we shall nevertheless bear
its stamp in our cognitive structures. Indeed, by abstractingspace and time
from existence and, hence, by creating the thing-in-itself,we also advance a new
mode of cognition whereby man comes witha priori conceptions, like space
and time in his sense-perception.The a priori pure reason, i.e. reason
before experiment,which is essentially theoretical reason, becomes a leading
frameof cognition to be filled with the results of experience whichKant cannot
dispense with. The thing-in-itself paved the way fortheoretical,
a priori pure reason, whereas phenomenainspire hope in terms
of experiment. That is why with Kant, knowledgeis theoretical and experimental.
It is obvious that if we forgetthe thing-in-itself and regard phenomena as an
objective reality,the cognition professed by Kant is actually modern scientific
cognition. The Critique of Pure Reason invites to that
theoretical insight which was responsible for the birth of quantummechanics or
of such theoretical concepts to which we seek toadapt experimental facts.
Additionally, it has made possible increasinglycomplex and refined experiments.
In the second edition to The Critique of Pure Reason, Kant
explained why he consideredphysics to be a theoretical knowledge of reason.
Thus, reasonmust determine the object of physics, he argues. Physicists should
understand that "reason only perceives that which it producesafter its
own design; that it must not be content to follow, asit were, in the
leading-strings of nature, but must proceed inadvance with principles of
judgment according to unvarying laws,and compel nature to reply to its
questions"4.And later
on, he added: "It is only the principles of reasonwhich can give to
concordant phenomena the validity of laws, andit is only when experiment is
directed by these rational principlesthat it can have any real utility.
Reason must approach naturewith a view, indeed, of receiving information from it,
not, however,in the character of a pupil, who listens to all that his master
chooses to tell him, but in that of a judge, who compels his witnessesto reply
to those questions which he himself thinks fit to
propose"5.
Modern science advances no doubt along theselines and finds in Kant one of its
spiritual fathers. Kant himself overlooks that phenomena areonly phenomena, and
regards them to be objects of research. Thushe finds that the principles for the
determination of phenomenain time
are6 :
- "All substances, in so far as they can be perceived inspace at the same
time, exist in a state of complete reciprocityof action";
- "In all changes of phenomena, substanceis permanent, and the quantum
thereof in nature is neither increasednor diminished";
- "All changes take place accordingto the law of the connection of Cause
to Effect".
As can be noticed, Kant reverts to ordinarylanguage, even if he considered
substance to be a phenomenonand nature to be a chain of
phenomena. If we overlook theconcept of thing-in-itself and if a priori
means the theoreticalmodel, then, with rare exceptions, Kant's whole
knowledgeis a scientific knowledge in its own right as long as
further difficulties do not come up.
The thing-in-itself failed to solve the issueof existence, but it has challenged
one to re-think it. In thisway Kant unravelled philosophically the breadth of
modern science,the role of theoretical languages in approaching reality and the
confrontation of theoretical concepts with experience.
Save for the questionable initial solution(which consists in driving space and
time from the objective existenceto assign them to the subject alone), Kant's
attempt to get outof the deadlock was of fair scientific accuracy.
The Limit of the Thing-in-Itself10